Monday, October 17, 2022

Terry J. Wright on John Calvin's Nestorian-Leaning Christology

  

The Divided Mediator

 

Clearly, Calvin wishes to focus on the one person of the Mediator rather than the two natures that constitute him; but despite this intention, he has a tendency not only to distinguish between Christ’s two natures, but also to isolate them from one another. In doing so, Calvin balances precariously over a trap that he thinks he avoids completely: he posits a Nestorian division with the persons of Christ (Calvin denies that his Christology if Nestorian; see Calvin, Institutes, 2:14:4, 486). According to Roger Helland, such a near-Nestorian view ‘attributes [Christ’s] supernatural miracles, knowledge and power to his deity, while attributing his tiredness, temptations, trials, thirst, and emotions to his humanity’, with the danger that Christ is presented as ‘some sort of schizophrenic divine-man who functions back and forth between his two natures’ (R. Helland, ‘The Hypostatic Union: How Did Jesus Function?’, Evangelical Quarterly 65 [1993], 311-327 [325-326]). This leads us to identify two problems with Calvin’s Christology. First, Calvin makes too sharp a distinction between Christ’s two natures so that it is impossible to see how they actually related; and secondly, Christ’s divine nature is emphasised to such an extent that his human nature is rendered superficial. Both these problems are exacerbated by Calvin’s use of the communicatio idiomatum, which ironically he employs to overcome these problems, and stem from his use of the body-soul simile. . . . Calvin seems not to address the matter of how the two natures truly related in Christ and so risks affirming a division in the Mediator. If the Mediator is divided, if his humanity and his divinity are so distinct that there is no positive relation between them, then we have good cause to doubt the effectiveness of his work of atonement. Against the orthodox understanding of the Son suffering death as a man, we would instead have the Son suffering death in his humanity whilst his divinity lives on – and this raises the question of how truly he was united to his humanity at the start. To compensate for his strong emphasis on the distinction between Christ’s two natures, Calvin employs the communicatio idiomatum; but this does not resolve the matter, for ‘the things that [Christ] carried out in his human nature are transferred improperly, although not without reason, to his divinity” (Calvin, Institutes, 2:14:2, 484, emphasis mine). The communicatio for Calvin effectively is a conceptual aid to affirm the relation between the two distinct natures rather than an attempt to clarify that relation. There is, however, no actual communicatio, and no sense, as Bruce McCormack suggests, that a rhetorical understanding of the communicatio is possible precisely due to an actual communicatio (McCormack, For Us and Our Salvation, 8-9), that is, the Incarnation of the Word. . . . This in turn impacts the genuineness of Christ’s humanity. If the notion of a divided Mediator raises the possibility that the Son suffers death in his humanity whilst his divinity lives on, as we have said, then there is always a docetic suggestion that the Son’s humanity is little more than a garment to be discarded upon death. Insofar as the Son of God assumes humanity to execute God’s will in created space and time, Christ’s flesh is the clothing in which the divine will is dressed and so impotent apart from the divinity that wears it. Calvin not only divides Christ’s activity between what he does as a man and what he does as divine, but presents the former, human action as somewhat incidental for achieving salvation:

 

our Lord came forth as true man and took the person and the name of Adam in order to take Adam’s place in obeying the Father, to present our flesh as the price of satisfaction to God’s righteous judgment, and, in the same flesh, to pay the penalty that we deserved. In short, since neither as God alone could he feel death, nor as man alone could he overcome it, he coupled human nature with divine that to atone for sin he might submit the weakness of the one to death; and that, wrestling with death by the power of the other nature, he might win victory for us. (Calvin, Institutes, 2:12:3, 466, emphasis mine)

 

The problem is that this presents Christ as more than human, a tertium quid; he has a divine component from which to draw resources, something that no other human can claim. Whilst it is true that Jesus is the Son of God, the word made flesh, this means neither that he has some intrinsic power to utilise to achieve God’s purposes for the world, nor that somehow the Word causes the actions of the humanity he assumes. To affirm the incarnation is to say no more than the Son of God took humanity to himself and now lives as a man. Although Jesus of Nazareth is unique insofar as no other human can claim truthfully to be the Word made flesh, there is no ontological difference between him and any other human. This means that when he was tempted to disobey his father and so to refuse his calling, Jesus resisted not because of some inner faculty but through the empowerment of the Holy Spirit. Indeed, Jesus’s faithfulness to God fundamentally is something prompted and enabled by the Spirit, who himself is the pledge of God’s faithfulness to the whole of his creation through his action in Christ. Calvin’s pneumatology, so clearly present when he discussed the human relation to God through Christ (See, for example, Calvin, Institutes, 3:1:1, 537-538), is curiously absent from the constitution of the person of Christ. (Terry J. Wright, Providence Made Flesh: Divine Presence as a Framework for a Theology of Providence [Paternoster Theological Monographs; Eugene, Oreg.: Wipf and Stock, 2009], 203, 205, 206-7)

 

Blog Archive