Wednesday, November 23, 2022

Robin M. Jensen (RC) on Early Christian Attitudes Towards Icon Veneration

  

Marcus Minucius Flex, Octavius

 

The pagan Caecilius presents many objections to Christian practices, among them the absence of pictorial depictions of the Christian deity. He contends that this deficiency is objectively perverse and incriminating. . . . In reply, Octavius admits that Christians do not make images of their god but insists that this is not because the deity is disgraceful but because God is invisible. The Christian god, he continues, does not inhabit a temple, cannot be contained by any human-made structure, and cannot be localized in any earthly dwelling. . . . rather than simply claiming that Christianity’s lack of images and temples demonstrates its rational and moral superiority, Octavius ridicules visual representations of polytheists’ gods. He declares that is it simple  minded to offer prayers or gifts to cult images and especially to be beguiled by costly or beautiful objects made by artisans from silver, bronze, ivory, or gold. Worshiping insensate objects crafted by human hands from base materials subject to ruse and decay is absurd. Such things can harbor nests of mice and are often covered with spiders’ webs or birds’ droppings. The idol makers are themselves lewd, depraved, and immoral. (Oct. 24.5) . . . Perhaps because arguments from Christian scripture would be unpersuasive to his polytheist rival, Octavius never refers to the Mosaic commandments against graven images (e.g., Exod 20:4). Somewhat ironically, he even contradicts Caecilius’s favorable description of monotheistic Jews worshiping their God with altars and temples. He insists that Jews did so only in the distant past, before God abandoned them because they had deserted the Law. (Oct. 11, 33). (Robin M. Jensen, From Idols to Icons: The Rise of the Devotional Image in Early Christianity [Oakland, Calif.: University of California Press, 2022], 3, 4-5)

 

Although certainly fictional, Octavius’s disparagement of polytheists’ cult images aligns with attitudes widely espoused by early Christian apologists. Like him, they accentuated the similarity of their views with the negative judgment of philosophers toward those who paid homage to gods’ statues. And like Minucius Felix’s character, they rarely called upon biblical condemnation of idolatry or vaunted the importance of Christianity’s Jewish roots. Even though scattered references to the Decalogue and a presumed Jewish repudiation of cult images can be found in the writings of Clement of Alexandria, Tertullian, and Origen, these were not major parts of their theological arsenal against idols. (For citations of the Decalogue, see Clement, Strom. 5.5; Tertullian, Idol. 3.3-4; Origen, Cels. 4.31; also Firmicus Maternus, Err. prof. rel. 28 [where he also cites Wis 15:15-17; Ps 134:15-18; Ep Jer 6; Isa 42:17) More often, second- and third-century Christian writers ridiculed the images of Greco-Roman gods with tropes similar to Octavius’s. In particular, they mocked polytheists as gullibly believing that inanimate human-made statues, fabricated by artisans from base materials (e.g., wood, stone, or metal), deserved any form of veneration. Also like Octavius, they cautioned that the statues might be contaminated by malevolent beings.

 

Christian critics judged that paying homage to material objects fundamentally misunderstands the difference between the unstable, sensible realm and the unchanging, intelligible one—it confuses appearances with reality. Such lack of discernment could be corrected only by retraining patterns of thought, reassessing the nature of sensory perception, and cultivating spiritual comprehension. Yet in this view, the problem was not the images themselves but rather the unwarranted value or intrinsic spiritual power attributed to them. This attribution was delusional in itself, but the delusion was compounded because these objects depicted false or powerless gods. Once again, the gods themselves were not the real problem: devotes endangered themselves by becoming duped by demons who fraudulently took on the appearances and names of those (false) gods. (Ibid., 5)

 

Athenagoras of Athens (d. ca. 190)

 

[Athenagoras] castigated those who venerated images for their failure to distinguish matter from God, the sacred from the profane, or the created from the uncreated. He contended that things known only through the bodily senses are utterly different from what is mentally apprehended, adding that the two are as far apart as artists and their materials. His sharp critique includes a statement that exemplifies the view that created matter is fundamentally incompatible with the Divine Being:

 

Since the multitude, not being able to distinguish what a gulf there, is between God and matter, approach with reverence material idols, are we on their account to come forward and worship their statues when we know and distinguish created from uncreated, being from non-being, intellect from sense, and give each its proper name? If God and matter are the same, two names for the one thing, then we are atheists for not reverencing as gods stones and good, gold, and silver. But if they are utterly different, as far apart as the craftsman from the materials of his trade, why are we being accused? . . . Even so, with God and matter, it is not matter that has the just praise and honour for the arrangement of beautiful things, but its maker, God. Therefore, if we consider the forms of matter to be gods, we shall be deemed blind to the true God for equating fragile and mortal things with the eternal. (Leg. 15)

 

Athenagoras evidently believed that his assertion that created matter is incapable of transmitting or representing the Divine Being also had to account for why images of pagan deities appeared to make things happen. It is unlikely, he explains, that dead objects can move themselves; they must have an internal mover. He denies, however that gods produce these effects in their statues. Like Minucius Felix’s Octavius, he claims that malevolent spirits usurp the gods’ names and animate these objects. (Leg. 23) Moreover, he says, these demons receive sustenance by inhabiting the images. They are eager to attract worshipers to idols because they consume the blood of sacrificial animals and the fragrant smoke waiting from the roasting flesh of the latter. (Leg. 26-27) (Robin M. Jensen, From Idols to Icons: The Rise of the Devotional Image in Early Christianity [Oakland, Calif.: University of California Press, 2022], 6)

 

Clement of Alexandria (150-215)

 

Rather than focusing on objects as such, he emphasized the problem of ontological misperception, reflecting the influence of Platonic disparagement of sense knowledge. He argued that since likenesses are inferior to their models, to regard visual representations as real—as any sense—is to mistake tangible things for transcendent things. In his Exhortation to the Greeks, Clement ridicules those who set up blocks of wood or pillars of stone alone with images of gods in human form and includes a rare citation of the biblical prohibition against making graven likenesses of anything in heaven or on earth. (protrep. 4) Here he even appears to attack all representational art, describing it in Platonic terms as imitative at best and deceptive at worst. He recognizes that arts can make beautiful objects but maintains that when beauty is applied to the service of false gods, it gives these non-existences unjustified and dangerously seductive splendor. (Protep. 4; cf. Plato, Rep. 10) In his treatise The Stromata, Clement again cites the Decalogue’s prohibition of graven images, explaining that it was intended to inhibit overattachment to material things and reiterating his belief that giving homage to sensible things dishonors those that are purely intelligible and immaterial. (Strom. 5.5) Elsewhere in The Stromata, Clement cites the commandment against theft rather than the prohibition of graven images, denouncing those who make images because they steal God’s prerogative as the unique creator. (Strom. 6.16) Clement then has to explain how this god, who prohibited graven figures, could have ordered Moses to make two golden cherubim to guard the Ark of the Covenant (Exod. 25:18-21). These, he asserts, were merely allegorical figures and not actual beings, whose features were mystical references to the rational soul and its spiritual repose. (Strom. 5.6) (Robin M. Jensen, From Idols to Icons: The Rise of the Devotional Image in Early Christianity [Oakland, Calif.: University of California Press, 2022], 6-7)

 

Origen:

 

[Origen, like Clement of Alexandria] acknowledged that Jews and Christians are not alone in questioning the validity of god’s images. IN the first section of is refutation of Celsus, Origen notes that Celsus regarded Christian attitudes towards idols as justified but also far from unique, insofar as their arguments against image worship had already been made by Heraclitus, Zeno of Citium, and others. (Cels. 1.5; see also Athenagoras, Leg. 6). Later in this treatise, Origen summarizes Celsus’s defense of his coreligionists, Celsus asserts that Christians have misconstrued the ways that polytheists understand their images of the gods. Only the most naïve, he insists, see such things as divine in themselves. He cites Heraclitus (ca. 535-475 BCE), who compared the worshipers venerating statues to simpletons conversing with walls and not knowing which deities they address. Celsus then contends that Christians go too far by despising all images without realizing that such things are merely offerings consecrated to the gods’ service and vehicles for directing prayers to their depicted deities. They are not, he insists, deemed to be gods in themselves. Origen responds that Christians, in fact, do know the god to whom they direct their prayers and that this god cannot be addressed through images and is utterly unlike the polytheists’ deities, who are, he maintains merely demons. He adds that those polytheists who know better but simply pretend to honor the images out of custom set a bad example and, by so doing encourage ignorant attitudes. (Cels. 7.62, 7.65-66, 8.17-18)

 

Origen’s exchange with Celsus not only highlights the nature of the debate but shows that Christian critics likely understood that it was unjust to characterize polytheistic veneration of images simply as the unwitting attribution of life or power to insensate and human-made objects. They appreciated that ancient philosophers argued that although the images were not in themselves living deities, they were means by which devotees paid homage to the gods they depicted. Plato put it succinctly: “We set up statues [of the gods] as images, and we believe that when we worship these, lifeless though they be, the living gods beyond feel great good-will toward us and gratitude.” (Plato, Leg. 11.93IAI-4) (Robin M. Jensen, From Idols to Icons: The Rise of the Devotional Image in Early Christianity [Oakland, Calif.: University of California Press, 2022], 24)

 

Origen, like Clement, invoked Jewish reticence about figurative art, citing the biblical injunctions against idols in his refutation of the earlier polytheist Celsus. There he notes Celsus’s contention that if, according to Saint Paul, idols were nothing (1 Cor 8:4), there could be no harm in them. Even if they were actually demons, they would therefore be God’s creatures and deserve some kind of propitiation. Responding in terms much like those of Minucius Felix and Athenagoras, Origen maintains that if idols are nothing, any association with them is liable to mean association with demons. (Cels. 8.24) These demons, he says, are invited into gods’ statues through rituals, consecration, or other magical arts. Once ensconced, they savor sacrificial foods and gratify illicit pleasures. (Ibid., 7)

 

Tertullian:

 

In his Apology, Tertullian also recounts the legacy of ancient Roman aniconism and proposes that Christians—at least in this regard—are more authentically Roman than the polytheists he scorns. (Apol. 25) In his Treatise against the Nations, Tertullian adds that the Roman Senate often prohibited worship of certain gods and forbade their altars. This he maintains, anti-image attitudes preexisted Christianity. (Nat. 1.10.41) In his treatise On Idolatry, Tertullian claims not only that aniconic religions preexisted Christianity but also that Satan introduced effigies of deities, along with their artificers. Prior to that, religion did without them. (Idol. 3) (Robin M. Jensen, From Idols to Icons: The Rise of the Devotional Image in Early Christianity [Oakland, Calif.: University of California Press, 2022], 30-31)

 

Despite al this fulmination against idolatry, Tertullian does not appear to regard most pictorial or figurative religious artworks as idols per se. Yet he dos judge the producers of such objects as complicit with idolatry, insofar as their use is potentially idolatrous, whatever the artisans’ craft (e.g., painting, sculpture, or weaving) and whether or not the objects have human forms or appearances (e.g., portraits of gods): “For it makes no difference whether a modeler forms the idol, an engraver chisels it out or an embroiderer weaves it, because it is also not important whether the idol is made of gypsum or colors or stone or bronze or silver or thread. For since even without an idol there may be idolatry, certainly, when the idol is present, its material and formal nature makes no difference, lest one should think that only that must be regarded as an idol which has been consecrated in human shape.” (Idol. 1.1-3) (Ibid., 8)

 

Council of Elvira and Canon 36:

 

One often noted witness to the likelihood that Christians owned and even venerated portraits of holy persons by the fourth century comes from the compiled acts of the Council of Elvira, usually dated to 300-306. The Spanish regional council dealt with a number of church disciplinary issues, including a concern about images, addressed by canon 36. This brief canon simply states: “There shall be no pictures in churches, lest what is reverence and adored be depicted on walls.” The wording implies not wariness about art in general and much less about narrative subjects but rather caution about depicting certain types of figures (i.e., sacred things worthy of adoration on church walls. The kinds of artworks that would have attracted the reverence to which the canon refers were most likely frontal portraits of Christ, the apostles, and other saints. Presumably, at least some Christians must have been prone to venerating or praying to them, or there would have been no need for such a ruling. While this might not be direct and early evidence for a cult of icons as such, concern about such behavior suggests something similar. (Robin M. Jensen, From Idols to Icons: The Rise of the Devotional Image in Early Christianity [Oakland, Calif.: University of California Press, 2022], 93)

 

Eusebius of Caesarea

 

A second commonly cited fourth-century criticism of images [alongside the Council of Elvira] comes from another source attributed to Eusebius of Caesarea, a letter in which he replies to a request from the emperor Constantine’s sister Constantia. She evidently asked him to provide a portraits of Christ that she could use for her personal devotions. Although Eusebius seems fairly tolerant of image veneration in his account of the statue of Jesus with the haemorrhaging woman (explaining that Gentile converts could be expected to continue with some of their old practices), this letter expounds a far more negative line, particularly in regard to images of Christ. Refusing Constantia’s appeal, Eusebius explains that what she wants is impossible.

 

Part of his concern was most likely the fact that images of Jesus are categorically different from images of saints or biblical characters, insofar as Jesus is divine. Showing almost prescient cognizance of the complex arguments that would be deployed in Christological debates of the fifth century, Eusebius framed the problem somewhat like the Apostle John did in his rebuke of Lycomedes. Portraying only Christ’s external appearance heretically divides his inseparable human and divine natures. Because no artist could represent Christ’s invisible, uncircumscribable divine nature, the portrait would be no more than an inanimate imitation of the temporally conditioned form he assumed in his incarnation.

 

What sort of image of Christ are you seeking? It is the true and unalterable one which bears His essential characteristics, or the one which He took up for our sake when He assumed the form of a servant? [Phil. 2:7] . . . Granted, He has two forms, even I do not think that your request has to do with His divine form . . . Surely then, you are seeking His image as a servant, that of the flesh which He put on for our sake. But that, too, we have been taught was mingled with the glory of His divinity so that the mortal part was swallowed up by Life [2 Cor 5:4] . . . How can one paint an image of so wondrous and unattainable a form—if the term ‘form’ is t all applicable to the divine and spiritual essence—unless, like the unbelieving pagans, one is to represent things that bear no possible resemblance to anything . . .? For they, too, make such idols when they wish to mould the likeness of what they consider to be a god or, as they might say, one of the heroes or anything else of the kind, yet are unable even to approach a resemblance, and do delineate and represent some strange human shapes. Surely, even you will agree that such practices are not lawful for us. (Letter to Constantia [PG 20:154])

 

Toward the end of his letter, Eusebius adds an interesting detail that echoes one of his passing comments in the story of the statue at Paneas: that a woman once presented him with a picture of two men in the guise of philosophers and alleged that they were depictions of Paul and Christ. Declaring that he had no idea where she obtained the picture or why she mistakenly believed that it represented the apostle and the Savior, he reports that he confiscated the offensive object, as he worried that her displaying it would make others regard her as an idol worshipper. . . . If it is genuine (or even partly so) and taken together with his mention of the statue group at Paneas, then Eusebius seems to have been aware that portraits of Christ and the apostles not only existed but had become objects of devotional use and actual veneration. (Robin M. Jensen, From Idols to Icons: The Rise of the Devotional Image in Early Christianity [Oakland, Calif.: University of California Press, 2022], 93-94, comment in square brackets added for clarification)

 

Augustine of Hippo:

 

In the early fifth century, Augustine likewise understood that polytheists distinguished between veneration of an idol and the transfer of honor to the being the idol represented. Still, he condemned the practice of making images for veneration. In a sermon preached around 404, Augustine railed against those who think they can fashion images of the gods, because they demean themselves by worshiping things lower than themselves. He allowed that these deluded folks believe they can reasonably defend their practices by distinguishing between the objects and the invisible numinia, or spirits, of the images. He even offered what he assumed to be their response: “We too know that idols are empty show; but they are not what we worship . . . [We worship] the numina of the idols. We do indeed do homage to what we can see, but we worship what we cannot see” (Serm. 23B). Then, echoing earlier Christian apologists, Augustine retorted that these so-called invisible numina are not divine beings lying behind the images but evil demons disguised as gods.

 

In another sermon, on Psalm 113, Augustine acknowledges that some polytheists deny that they irrationally venerate mundane objects. They clam that they are not deluded, that they honor the deities that the objects represent and now the objects themselves. Nevertheless, he observes, even people who perceive themselves as above such misconceptions or interpret these images as mere signs pointing beyond themselves get entangled in old habits and superstitions. He notes that those who worship a transcendent body like the sun tend to pray to a statue of Sol. Why, he asks, would they turn their backs to the actual sun to pray to a powerless object? (Enarrat. Ps. 113[2]) (Robin M. Jensen, From Idols to Icons: The Rise of the Devotional Image in Early Christianity [Oakland, Calif.: University of California Press, 2022], 26-27)

 

The following notes are also important:


 

The Fourth-Century Material Turn

 

In recent decades, historians have applied new methods and theories to the study of the material and visual dimensions of religious observance. The roles that various kinds of objects, mages, architectural spaces, and geographical places play in forming concepts about the divine realm and its degree of accessibility to human perception are now significant subjects of academic investigation. A crucial development in fourth-century Christian practice, often referred to as the material turn, evinces a change in attitude that reconsidered the potential of the external, sensible world to mediate invisible, spiritual, and divine realities. This development, what one scholar calls a “shift in . . . sensibility,” especially credited the sense as reliable faculties for approaching or encountering the sacred. (Miller, Corporeal Imagination, 3)

 

Philosophical speculation about the relationship of form to matter—influenced by Aristotelian philosophy, which insists that form cannot exist without matter (or soul without body)—was essential to early Christian doctrine about the goodness of creation and, in particular, the possibility of bodily resurrection. Nevertheless, the observable changeability and corruptibility of material things raised doubts about their worthiness. Platonist assertions that the sensible world is transient an that the identity and value of physical objects derive from their timeless and transcendent prototypes underlie Christian denigration of cult images as futile and misguided. As Athenagoras remarked, those who venerate images constructed from matter and thus regard matter as divine do not distinguish God from matter or discern the enormous distance between them. By contrast, he insisted, Christians do not make the created for the uncreated or bring for nonbeing, and therefore they refuse to put what which is perishable on the same plane with that which is eternal. (Athenagoras, Leg. 15)

 

Thus, early Christian apologists apparently found little—if any—religious significance in objects fabricated by human hands from tangible material. Although archaeological evidence shows that second- and third-century Christians owned and used special buildings, vessels, books, and even pictorial art in their religious practice, they did not regard these as conduits for the holy, even if they did not judge them to be idolatrous. (Robin M. Jensen, From Idols to Icons: The Rise of the Devotional Image in Early Christianity [Oakland, Calif.: University of California Press, 2022], 143)

 

Most polytheists undoubtedly realized that statues were not actually gods even as they may have viewed certain ones as distinctly venerable, whether by reason of age, beauty, or history. Although not completely identified with the deities they depicted, these images testified to their existence. Thus, no simple distinction between representation and reality is possible, partly because many ancients did in fact believe that images could mediate the presence of transcendent being and that these beings were the intended recipients of devotees’ prayers, adoration, or offerings. The link between the deities and their effigies is complicated. Even allowing that their circumstances or setting could vary, these images and the immortals they represent are of different natures, none is made of base materials, inert, mute, and vulnerable to decay, while the other is immaterial, transcendent, and eternal. Yet they are united in some sense, insofar as the model conceptually or symbolically points to the original. (Robin M. Jensen, From Idols to Icons: The Rise of the Devotional Image in Early Christianity [Oakland, Calif.: University of California Press, 2022], 19)

 

Surviving documentary evidence attests that from the second century CE onward, certain church authorities observed devotional practices among Christians that, in their judgment, approximated idolatrous or heretical adoration of holy images. This concern grew more pronounced in the fourth and fifth centuries, even while many apparently tolerated narrative iconographic programs in cemeteries and churches. It was, after all, in the fourth century that portrait-type depictions of Christ, his mother Mary, and the saints gradually appeared and began to replace the older narrative subjects. These new types were installed in mosaic on church apses, woven into curtains, parented on tomb walls, and rendered on portable wooden panels. With only a few exceptions, they were not three-dimensional figures and in this respect in particular contrasted with traditional Greco-Roman cult statues. (Robin M. Jensen, From Idols to Icons: The Rise of the Devotional Image in Early Christianity [Oakland, Calif.: University of California Press, 2022], 90)

 

Even as Christian writers continued their condemnation of so-called pagan idolatry, a dramatic turn toward material forms of Christian practice during the fourth century changed the context as well as the dimensions of the critique. Contemporaneous with the shift in Christian social and political status during the reign of Constantine I (306-37 CE). Christians began to make two-dimensional images of Christ and the saints without narrative contexts, an evolution that corresponds with the rise of the cult of relics and was possibly directly linked to the visits of pilgrims to saints’ tombs and sacred places associated with the life of Christ. While such portrait-type images might not have been worshiped or venerated in the same manner as pagan cult images, and were almost never statues in the round, they do point to a change in the ways that Christians appraised the value of images as instruments capable of facilitating encounters with the holy persons they depicted. Like the emperor’s portrait set up to act as his representative presence or the consecrated elements of the eucharist, these images soon served as means of connecting the pious viewed with their heaven-dwelling or otherwise absent models. (Robin M. Jensen, From Idols to Icons: The Rise of the Devotional Image in Early Christianity [Oakland, Calif.: University of California Press, 2022], xviii-xix)

 


Further Reading:

 

Answering Fundamentalist Protestants and Roman Catholic/Eastern Orthodox on Images/Icons

 

 

Blog Archive