Friday, November 22, 2024

Gilbert J. Garraghan on the Argument from Silence

  

The Argument from Silence

 

¶ 149 The argument from silence aims to prove the non-reality of an alleged fact from the circumstance that contemporary or later sources of information fail to say anything about it. It is sometimes misleadingly called the negative argument; but this can easily be taken to mean something false, namely, that the argument rests on an explicit denial of some fact. A writer’s silence regarding a fact may be because of ignorance, or by deliberate omission, or from lapse of memory.

 

(a) To be valid, the argument from silence must fulfil two conditions: the writer whose silence is invoked in proof of the non-reality of an alleged fact, would certainly have known about it had it been a fact; knowing it, he would under the circumstances certainly have made mention of it. When these two conditions are fulfilled, the argument from silence proves its point with moral certainty. Both conditions have their explanation in the human instincts which urge us to ascertain the truth, as also to give expression to it when self-interest so requires.

 

(b) In applying the argument from silence, the first step is to be determine by rigorous analysis of the evidence whether or not the conditions laid down really exist. The first condition presupposes that the alleged fact was of some importance, was easily knowable, and would certainly have come directly or indirectly to the notice of the informant whose silence regarding it is under examination. The second condition presupposes that suppression of the fact would have been prejudicial to the informant by compromising his reputation for honor, justice, patriotism, leaning; by injuring his family, political party, religious denomination; or by giving comfort and aid to his enemies. (Gilbert J. Garraghan, A Guide to Historical Method, ed. Jean Delanglez [New York: Fordham University Press, 1946], 162)

 

¶ 151 CAUTIONS IN THE USE OF THE ARGUMENT FROM SILENCE

 

In using this argument from silence two cautions are recommended.

 

(a) In our modern age with its immense facilities for the communication of news, an event of importance no sooner happens than it becomes known far and wide, among all classes of people. But such was not the case in earlier times. Because of poor means of communication, events of major interest and importance could remain unknown for long periods of time, even to persons in high position, even though they could command all existing sources of information on current happenings. Instances in point, so astonishing that one would scarcely credit them if they were not attested by unimpeachable evidence, are on record.

 

(b) Present-day standards in the selection of data for historical record often differ from those which obtained among the ancient and medieval authors. They had their own ideas as to what was important and unimportant, and hence could easily pass over in silence incidents or facts which might appear to us in every way deserving of record.

 

Many incidents may be adduced of the most extraordinary silence of historians relative to facts with which they must have been acquainted and which seemed to lie directly in the course of their narrative. Important facts are mentioned by no ancient writer though they are unquestionably established by the evidence of existing inscriptions, coins, statues, or buildings.—Isaac Taylor, The Transmission of Ancient Books to Modern Times together with the Process of Historical Proof (Liverpool, 1875), 120.

 

¶ 152 St. Augustine knew (ca. 405) nothing of the great orthodox Synod of Sardica, ca. 343-344, though he was aware of the parallel Arain Council held at that same time, and alter in the neighboring Philipopolis. He was also informed as to the great controversial writings of St. Athanasius and St. Hilary, which make frequent mention of the same Synod of Sardica. Again, when St. Augustine was consecrated bishop, neither he nor the aged Bishop of Carthage, Valerian, was aware of the eighth canon of the Council of Nice, which forbade that two bishops have their sees simultaneously in the same city.—Feder, Lehrbuch, 284 f.

 

Josephus makes no mention of the massacre of the infants in Bethlehem. Either he never heard of the incident, or if he did, he probably thought the massacre of a few infants too minor an incident in the criminal career of Herod to deserve record.—Constant Fouard, The Christ, the Son of God, 1:72.

 

Numerous long-standing problems bearing on legends, traditions, and the authorship or authenticity of writings have been satisfactorily solved by critical use of the argument from silence. On the other hand, attempts to apply it in certain cases have been unsuccessful. (Gilbert J. Garraghan, A Guide to Historical Method, ed. Jean Delanglez [New York: Fordham University Press, 1946], 163-64)

 

 

 

To Support this Blog:

 

Patreon

Paypal

Venmo

Amazon Wishlist

Email for Amazon Gift card: ScripturalMormonism@gmail.com

Blog Archive