Sunday, March 16, 2025

David Brown on Limitations to Anselm's Apologetic

  

ANSELM’S APPROACH AND ITS LIMITATIONS

 

It is clear from this brief survey of his writings that Anselm deploys aesthetic considerations in two rather different ways: sometimes as an argument in itself for a particular conclusion, more commonly as confirmation that a particular conclusion is the correct one. Another way of making this distinction is to observe that, whereas for Anselm ‘not fitting’ entails ‘necessarily not true of God’ (cf. Why God Became Man: 2.8), ‘fitting does not of itself automatically carry the same necessity. Both versions, however, rely on the same presupposition that God is beauty and everything derived from the divine must therefore partake of the same characteristic. In doing so, Anselm displays a confidence that few of us would have today. For many, perhaps most, in modern society, beauty is taken to be a purely subjective judgement, dependent on whatever happens to please the individual concerned. But even those who incline towards some objective standard would admit the difficulty of finding any easy reconciliation with questions of truth and goodness. So, for instance, few would deny that the rape scene in the Stanley Kubrick film A Clockwork Orange (1971), set to Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony, has the beauty of a ballet, yet it is hardly a good act. Such problems no doubt explain why there has been such a large- scale retreat from treating beauty as one of the transcendentals directly applicable to God.

 

But for Christianity the difficulties in fact run much deeper, since there is little evidence to suggest a consistent Christian position on the theme of beauty across the centuries. Thus in Anselm’s case his understanding is in fact much more closely allied to notions originating in classical Greece than anything we find in scripture. Although in adopting such a view Anselm reflects the general patristic position, including that of Augustine, it is as well to note the tension. This is not to suggest that scripture must always function as the primary theological norm. It is simply to observe a tension of which Anselm himself was certainly unaware. The noted Old Testament scholar, Gerard von Rad, even maintained that ‘Israel lacked all critical reflection on the phenomenon of beauty’ (von Rad 1962: I, 365). While that is probably an exaggeration, his words do stand as a caution against Hans Urs von Balthasar’s over- confident deployment of the biblical ‘glory’ as an equivalent term (Balthasar 1982). Certainly, both Hebrew kabod and Greek doxa are used in an aesthetic sense, but the meaning seems more to do with what overwhelms with its magnificence or splendour rather than with Greek notions of elegance, balance, or proportion. Indeed, quite different words are used of ordinary human beauty (Penchansky 2013), and in the Hebrew scriptures kabod is only applied to the human when kings or others might potentially at least offer a similar splendour (e.g. Job 40:10). It is to the late Greek Book of Wisdom that one must turn before beauty in our world and in the divine are firmly linked as in the Greek hierarchical model, with God now described as ‘the author of beauty’ (13.3). However, in the Fathers even as early as Irenaeus we find aesthetic considerations of this kind being adduced for divine action, as, for example, in his arguments with the Gnostics over why there should only be four gospels (Against Heresies: III, xi, 8). By the time of Augustine, divine simplicity is firmly rooted aesthetically (as well as for other motives) and serves as an approach to the problem of evil that sees light and shade as integral to an adequate response (defended in Farrer 1962).

 

Yet to leave matters on this note of a bewildering variety of approaches to beauty would seem unfair to Anselm, not least because it appears a basic human intuition about the nature of divinity that it should embody all that we positively value, and so should include beauty. So, however great the problems, recent attempts to rescue beauty from the margins of discussions in philosophical theology (e.g. Tallon 2012) are surely to be welcomed. But perhaps the difficulties within Christianity should be seen as in large part self- generated, and it is here that Anselm may still have something to teach us. In marked contrast to much modern writing, he never declared Christ’s actual suffering on the cross beautiful; for him it was rather key aspects of the event that were beautiful and which helped determine the divine choice, such as the wood of the cross balancing the tree of the Fall, and so on. Instead, as noted above, Anselm remained remarkably restrained in his description of Christ’s sufferings. The pressure to talk of them as beautiful comes only if we suppose doxa to be concerned with essentially the same idea. But is it? When John and Paul talk of the divine ‘glory’ being revealed on the cross, is it not more like something that generates in us a sense of stupor and amazement? While there is no doubt an aesthetic element to such a response, to talk of it sharing anything with delight in beauty is surely perverse. What attracts our admiration and wonder is that a being so removed from such horrors deigns to identify with our experience of them, and so took on what had, in the words of Isaiah, ‘no form or comeliness that we should look at him, and no beauty that we should desire him’ (53.2). In other words, it is the entirely unexpected character of the event that gives it such revelatory significance, not any putative connection with beauty. The ‘glory’ of which the Bible speaks and which so much modern Christian writing has identified with beauty is really something quite different: a matter of revelation, not natural theology. With that much acknowledged, the beauty of which Anselm spoke and which derives from the Greek tradition can then continue to exercise an epistemological role in philosophical theology, in particular in shaping what is possible for human experience of God. How extensive these roles might be is too large a question to open here. (David Brown, “Anselm,” in The Oxford Handbook of The Epistemology of Theology, ed. William J. Abraham and Frederick D. Aquino [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017], 404-6)

 

 

To Support this Blog:

 

Patreon

Paypal

Venmo

Amazon Wishlist

Email for Amazon Gift card: ScripturalMormonism@gmail.com

Email for Logos.com Gift Card: IrishLDS87@gmail.com

Blog Archive