Monday, March 10, 2025

Enrico Mazza on Debates During the Medieval Period As To What An Animal Who Ate a Consecrated Host Consumed

  

WHAT DOES THE MOUSE EAT? (QUID MUS SUMIT?)

 

What does a mouse eat when it eats the eucharistic bread? Does it eat the Body of Christ or only the species? Is it possible to eat the species without thereby eating the Body of Christ?

 

Nowadays, this is an old-fashioned problem that, if anything, brings a smile to our contemporaries, but for the medieval thinkers it was a genuine problem from both a pastoral and a doctrinal standpoint, and its resolution brought into play all the theological and metaphysical principles at work in their teaching on the Eucharist. The first to raise the theological question was Berengarius of Tours in response to his objectors. If the physicist realism inaugurated by Paschasius and professed by Lanfranc of Bec and Humbert of Silva Candida were true, this conclusion would follow logically: The physical presence of the Body of Christ would be subject to the digestive processes not only of human beings but of animals and birds.

 

The question was an interesting one, and Guitmund of Aversa was the first to attempt an answer. He says that the true Body and Blood of Christ remain in the Sacrament even when this is eaten by an animal. He was not the only one to maintain this position, and Gary Macy tells us of other authors of that period who held it. Stephen Langton was the first to think that there would be a reverse transubstantiation, that is, that the bread would return at the moment when the mouse eats the Sacrament. The School of Laon, including William of Champeaux and William of St. Thierry, held that the mouse would eat only the eucharistic species and not the substance of the Body of Christ. Thomas Aquinas, on the other hand, maintained that what the mouse eats is the Body of Christ, because as long as the accidents of the bread remain incorrupt, they are a sign of the substance of the Body of Christ, and where the accidents are, there the substance of the Body of Christ likewise is (by way of the accidents).

 

Bonaventure held the opposite of Thomas’s view and, adopting a completely personal position, said that Christ is present under the species of this Sacrament only to the extent that the Sacrament is ordered to human use. Since its eating by a mouse cannot be described as coming under the use prescribed by Christ, it cannot be maintained that the mouse eats the Body of Christ. Thomas rejects this view outright as derogating from the truth of the Sacrament, while Bonaventure in response says that whatever be the value of Thomas’s opinion, his arguments do not prevent pious ears from refusing to listen to it being said that the Body of Christ is in the stomach of a mouse; he asserts that his opinion is the more common one and certainly the most appropriate and the most conformed to reason. Bonaventure was correct in saying that the more common opinion was that the mouse did not eat the Body of Christ; his personal contribution— the ordering of the Sacrament to human use—was a strong theological argument in favor of that opinion.

 

G. Macy calls attention to another fact that can explain the interest of the theologians in this obscure problem. Heretics, and especially the Cathars, used this question to prove that the Church’s teaching on the Eucharist was erroneous. The result was the rise of a current of thought which, in order to combat the heretics, maintained that the Body of Christ was not eaten by the mouse and did not descend into its stomach. In light of this finding of G. Macy we must admit that the response given at the end of the twelfth century and the beginning of the thirteenth was one that met a real pastoral problem: the defense of the faith against the Cathars.

 

The answers of Thomas and Bonaventure are more properly theological solutions, derived in each case from their systems and from the metaphysical principles on which their eucharistic teaching is based. It is worth noting that this minor question of the mouse enables us to see with greater clarity the difference between the eucharistic teaching of Thomas and that of Bonaventure: the former is more objectivist and more closely linked to the metaphysical analysis of being, while the latter is more closely linked to a personalist perspective that is based on the institution of the Sacrament by Christ, namely, that the Eucharist is for a human use, namely, for eating, and that this intended purpose determines the very nature of the eucharistic bread, inasmuch as a nonhuman use (eating by a mouse, for example) causes the cessation of sacramentality and the return of the substance of the bread. (Enrico Mazza, The Celebration of the Eucharist: The Origin of the Rite and the Development of Its Interpretation [Collegeville, Minn.: The Liturgical Press, 1999], 220-22)

 

 

 

To Support this Blog:

 

Patreon

Paypal

Venmo

Amazon Wishlist

Email for Amazon Gift card: ScripturalMormonism@gmail.com

Email for Logos.com Gift Card: IrishLDS87@gmail.com

Blog Archive